ABSTRACT Title of Thesis: MOTIVIC HOMOTOPY THEORY AND SYNTHETIC SPECTRA Charles Richard Dziedzic Master of Arts, 2024 Thesis Directed by: Professor Niranjan Ramachandran Department of Mathematics Motivic homotopy studies the application of techniques from homotopy theory to algebraic geometry, using A1 as the analogue of the unit interval. Voevodsky found early success in using his constructions to prove Milnor’s conjecture and the Bloch-Kato conjecture. An interesting and deep theory arises when constructing the unstable and stable motivic categories, and it has developed into its own field of study. We begin with a survey of these constructions, detailing the equivalences between the different model used in the construction of H(S) and SH(S). Here, we draw connections between all the constructions one might encounter across the literature, and provide explicit statements on their equivalence. Stable homotopy theorists have also found utility in motivic homotopy, using the stable mo- tivic homotopy category SH to advance computations of the stable homotopy groups of spheres, such as in the work of Isaksen-Wang-Xu. Other work by Bachmann-Kong-Wang-Xu has made great progress in our understanding of motivic homotopy theory. Synthetic spectra are a construction of Pstragrowski which represent a ‘return to form’ of some sort, as they are constructed entirely in the∞−category of spectra. However, they give rise to a natural bigrading and a strong connection to motivic homotopy; one of the main results is an equivalence of∞−categories with cellular motivic spaces over C, Spcell C . We build up enough of the general theory to establish the connection with motivic homotopy and comment on recent applications. MOTIVIC HOMOTOPY THEORY AND SYNTHETIC SPECTRA by Charles Richard Dziedzic Thesis submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Maryland, College Park in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts 2024 Advisory Committee: Professor Niranjan Ramachandran, Chair/Advisor Professor Jonathan M. Rosenberg Professor William M. Goldman © Copyright by Charles Richard Dziedzic 2024 Acknowledgments This thesis started out as a passion project, and every step of the process has been an enjoyable one. That isn’t to say that it has been a stress-free experience, and it would not have been possible without the support of a (not small) set of people. First and foremost, I would like to thank Professor Niranjan Ramachandran for suggesting the thesis topic, and encouraging me not to shy away from it despite the amount of background required. It is because of this guidance that I was able to learn so much throughout the process. I also want to thank Professor Jonathan Rosenberg for his many helpful comments on the drafts of this thesis, and for providing a neat, self-contained, and captivating introduction to motivic homotopy through his course in the spring of 2023. Finally, Professor Bill Goldman’s focus on telling a story while also seeing the ‘bigger picture’ in his lectures has shaped the way I think about mathematics – I thank him for this. I also am indebted to Professor Paul Goerss of Northwestern University. His mentorship and confidence in me are what inspired my strong curiosity for homotopy theory, and are the main reason I ended up pursuing graduate studies in mathematics. The support and encouragement of my friends Javier Reyes and Baidehi Chattopadhyay has been invaluable throughout my time writing this thesis. It is impossible to image how I would have managed the first two years of this program without them. ii Outside the world of mathematics, I owe my family special thanks for a lifetime of love, patience, and support. I especially could not have produced this thesis without the enduring support of my mother. iii Table of Contents Acknowledgements ii Table of Contents iv Chapter 1: Preliminaries 1 1.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 1.2 Simplicial Sets and Kan Complexes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2 1.3 Model Categories . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15 Chapter 2: Motivic Homotopy Theory 43 2.1 Grothendieck Topologies and Simplicial Presheaves . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43 2.2 Unstable Motivic Homotopy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50 2.3 Stable Motivic Homotopy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 60 2.4 Another Construction: P1−Spectra . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 68 2.5 Cellularity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 72 Chapter 3: An∞−Categorical Construction 76 3.1 The Language of∞−Categories . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 3.2 The Motivic Stable∞−Category . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 106 Chapter 4: Synthetic Spectra 110 4.1 Spherical Sheaves . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 110 4.2 Synthetic Spectra . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119 4.3 Synthetic Spectra as a Tool for Motivic Homotopy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 128 4.4 Applications and Recent Advances . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 143 Bibliography 147 iv Chapter 1: Preliminaries 1.1 Introduction The main goal of this thesis is to provide a self contained treatment of the construction of synthetic spectra and their relationship with motivic homotopy theory, culminating in the follow- ing result of Pstragowski (which is stated in loc. cit. as Theorem 4.3.35): Theorem 1.1.1 ([Pst23, Theorem 7.34]). The adjunction of∞−categories of Proposition 4.3.28 induces an adjoint equivalence of∞−categories (Spcell C )∧p (Synev MU)∧p (Θ∗)p ≃ Θ∗ between the p−completions for every prime p. To accomplish this goal, we first give some relevant background on simplicial model cate- gories in Chapter 1. Then, we construct the category of motivic spaces, and both the unstable and stable motivic homotopy categories in Chapter 2. In Chapter 3 we introduce (∞,1)−categories through the use of Joyal and Lurie’s theory of quasicategories, and then provide a construction of the stable motivic ∞−category. This is essential for our comparison with synthetic spectra. Finally, Chapter 4 gives the definitions and constructions for synthetic spectra, and proves our desired main result. 1 1.2 Simplicial Sets and Kan Complexes As a gentle introduction for the reader, we first give a few definitions of simplicial sets and Kan complexes. The standard reference is [GJ99]. Notation. We denote ∆ the category of ordinal numbers n, seen as a sequence 0 → 1 → 2 → ⋅ ⋅ ⋅→ n. The morphisms of this category are order-preserving maps. Alternatively, a object n can be thought of as a category with objects the increasing sequence of numbers, and morphisms the maps between including composition; then, maps between ordinal numbers are precisely functors between these categories. Definition 1.2.1. There are two classes of maps (functors) of ∆, which are the cofaces di ∶ n-1↪ n “skip i” codegeneracies si ∶ n+1↠ n “hit i twice,” where the cofaces are injective and codegeneracies surjective. There are a list of identities that these coface and codegeneracies must satisfy called the cosimplicial identities, and it is a standard exercise to check that these maps generate all maps in ∆. We present them here. 2 Definition 1.2.2. The cosimplicial identities are as follows: djdi = didj−1 if i < j sjdi = disj−1 if i < j sjdj = 1 = sjdj+1 sjdi = di−1sj if i > j + 1 sjsi = sisj+1 if i ≤ j Definition 1.2.3. A simplicial set is a presheaf of sets on ∆, S ∶∆op → Set. We use the notation Sn ∶= S(n) to denote the n−simplices of S. Definition 1.2.4. The category of simplicial sets, denoted S or Psh(∆), has objects simplicial sets, and morphisms maps of simplicial sets, i.e. natural transformations. More concisely, this is a presheaf category on ∆, also called a functor category. Example 1.2.5. The standard n-simplex ∆n is the simplicial set represented by n, ∆n ∶ hom∆(−,n) The Yoneda lemma then tell us that to study a simplicial set S, it suffices to study the functors (simplicial maps) of our standard n−simplex into the simplicial set S. To unpack this, the Yoneda 3 lemma gives us an isomorphism homS(∆n, S) = homS(hom∆(−,n), S) ≅ S(n) = Sn which explains the importance of this example (alternatively a definition or presented as an exer- cise in [GJ99]). With the introduction of the standard n−simplex, we are poised to introduce two partic- ularly important subcomplexes. However, we take a brief narrative sidestep to discuss the face and degeneracy maps. While we don’t have the topological framework one gets accustomed to when introduced to algebraic topology (with simplicial complexes) we can borrow some of the intuition. A simplicial set X has n−simplices the elements of Xn(= X(n)). The n + 1 face maps di =X(di),0 ≤ i ≤ n assign to x its n + 1 faces, where ‘faces’ means (n − 1)-simplices. Remark 1.2.6. Explicitly, on Xn our face map di takes a simplex x ∈Xn to the face di(x) ∈Xn−1 which does not contain the ith vertex. The case of degeneracies is a bit less intuitive at first thought but can be explained nicely. In the case of simplicial complexes, we have ‘hidden’ simplexes which have repeat vertices. For example, the standard 1−simplex ∣∆1∣ contains a degenerate 1−simplex as (0,0); this ‘looks’ like a point but is technically a 1-simplex. Remark 1.2.7. Explicitly, on Xn our degeneracy si takes a simplex x ∈ Xn and assigns it to the n + 1 simplex Definition 1.2.8. A simplicial set S′ is said to be a subset of the simplicial set S if there is a monomorphism S′ ↪ S. This means that S′n ⊂ Sn and if the face and degeneracies of S′ agree 4 with S; that is S(di)∣S′ = S′(di), S(si)∣S′ = S′(si). Definition 1.2.9. We let ιn ∈ hom∆(n,n) denote the identity map. The boundary of ∆n, ∂∆n, is the smallest subcomplex of ∆n containing the faces dj(ιn) for 0 ≤ j ≤ n. As such, we have ∂∆n j = ⎧⎪⎪⎪⎪⎪⎪⎪⎨⎪⎪⎪⎪⎪⎪⎪⎩ ∆n j if 0 ≤ j ≤ n − 1 degeneracies of ∆n k for 0 ≤ k ≤ n − 1 if j ≥ n We sometimes refer to this as the simplicial n−sphere, whose definition is sometimes re- formulated as follows: Definition 1.2.10. For our standard simplicial set ∆n, the ith face of ∆n, denoted ∂i∆n, is the simplicial subset generated by di ∈ ∆n n−1. In other words, it is the smallest simplicial subset of ∆n containing di. We then say that the simplicial n-sphere ∂∆n is the union of the faces ∂i∆n, 0 ≤ i ≤ n, a simplicial subset of ∆n; this is the simplicial subset generated by the maps di(ιn) ∈ ∆n n−1 for 0 ≤ i ≤ n. The simplicial sphere will be a key ingredient in our motivic stable homotopy category, but we don’t want to say too much on that now – it would ruin the ‘punchline.’ However, in support of the ultimate goal of introducing the realization-singular adjunction, it can be useful to describe ∂∆n in one other way, for which we want to provide some intuition. Coequalizers, as a colimit of a diagram, can naively be thought of as gluing constructions. The construction of ∂∆n can be seen as a gluing construction; consider ∂∆2. We want to glue together the faces ∂i(ιn) for 0 ≤ i ≤ 2, and this gluing is done along the simplicial sets ∆0, seen as the vertices 0,1,2 – yielding ∂∆2. This construction is generalized in higher dimensions; for 5 ∆n, we wish to glue together n−copies of ∆n−1, and this gluing should be done along 1 2n(n + 1) copies of ∆n−2. Concisely, we can state the definition as follows: Definition 1.2.11. The simplicial n−sphere ∆n is the following coequalizer ∐ 0≤i 0, U ∈ C and x0 ∈ X(U) the induced morphism f∗ ∶ πn(X ∣U , x0) → πn(Y ∣U , f(x0)) is an isomorphism. Definition 2.2.7. For C, τ a small site, the local projective model structure on sPsh(C) has: 1. Weak equivalences are the local weak equivalences described above, 2. fibrations are projective fibrations, i.e. those taken objectwise. 3. cofibrations the maps with the left lifting property with respect to acyclic fibrations. We can define the local injective model structure in the analagous way. The next results are essential to the“larger picture.” We connect the different (modern) ways of constructing the unstable motivic category (really, the category of spaces), and shows the equivalence of all the difference approaches one might find in the literature. These differences are rarely addressed in expository works, so we will draw special attention. Theorem 2.2.8. The left Bousfield localization LNis sPsh(SmS) (the Nisnevich local model cat- egory) has the local projective model structure. Proof. This result was first proved in [DHI03] (see the introduction, or section 6 for more explicit details). Taking the left Bousfield localizations with respect to hypercovers is a less common choice, 52 as the local projective (or injective) model structures are easy to work with, and its more imme- diately clear what the model structure looks like. Proposition 2.2.9. The local injective model structure and local projective model structure on sPsh(C) (and sSh(C)) are Quillen equivalent. Proof. This is from the identity functor applied the underlying category which are, of course, ad- joint. Quillen equivalence comes from the “symmetry” in the construction of projective (co)fibrations and injective (co)fibrations. This is discussed in [DHI03]. Remark 2.2.10. It is actually true, more generally, that the global projective model structure and the global injective model structure are Quillen equivalent, due to [DHI03]. So, our choice to using the projective structure is somewhat arbitrary, in the sense that our resulting homotopy (and stable homotopy) categories will be the same. The local projective structure actually ends up being a lot nicer than what we’ve described here, which is due to the work of Blander. We present the full statement below. Theorem 2.2.11 ([Bla01, Theorem 1.6]). Let T be any essentially small site. Then the category of simplicial presheaves on T sPsh(T ) with the local projective model structure is a proper simplicial cellular (so cofibrantly generated) model category. Remark 2.2.12. By remarks later, we will get some other results of [Bla01], namely an equiv- alence in the model category of simplicial sheaves and simplicial presheaves under the local projective structure. These also apply to the local injective structure. We are now ready to establish the category which is worth of the name “motivic spaces.” Simplicial (pre)sheaves provide a natural starting point for constructing a homotopy category, so we have an appropriate category of spaces now. However, a choice has to be made – do we 53 consider (simplicial) presheaves or sheaves? This is a choice that varies among authors, but we will rectify this. Lemma 2.2.13. For (C, τ) a (small) site, the inclusion functor ι ∶ sSh(C) → sPsh(C) has a left adjoint a ∶ sPsh(C) → sSh(C), which we will sometimes call the sheafification functor, or the associated sheaf functor. Proof. This is an immediate consequence of Theorem 2.1.8 Theorem 2.2.14. For a small site C, τ and the local projective model structure on sPsh(C) and sSh(C), the adjoint pair sSh(C) sPsh(C)ι a form a Quillen equivalence. The same holds for the local injective structure. Proof. This is a result initially from [Bla01]. A longer discussion (in textbook format) can be found in [Jar15]. So, to summarize all of the above results, we state our following result: Theorem 2.2.15. For C a small site, we have Quillen equivalences sShl.inj(C) ≃Q sPshl.inj(C) ≃Q sPshl.proj(C) ≃Q sShl.proj(C) where l.inj denotes the local injective model structure, and l.proj denotes the local projective model structure. As such, we have equivalence of categories Ho(sShl.inj(C)) ≃ Ho(sPshl.inj(C)) ≃ Ho(sPshl.proj(C)) ≃ Ho(sShl.proj(C)) 54 Proof. All of the above results. This is a general result for any site; we have our following corollary Corollary 2.2.16. There are Quillen equivalences LNis sShl.inj(SmS) ≃Q LNis sPshl.inj(SmS) ≃Q LNis sPshl.proj(SmS) ≃Q LNis sShl.proj(SmS) and thus equivalences on the corresponding homotopy categories. Proof. Immediate. Definition 2.2.17. We call the category LNis sPsh(SmS) with the (local) projective model struc- ture the category of motivic spaces, often denoted SpcS . Notation. We will sometimes refer to SpcS as sShNis(SmS) instead of LNis sPsh(SmS). This is understood to be the category sPsh(SmS) with the (proper, cellular, combinatorial simplicial) local projective model structure. Remark 2.2.18. The way we have constructed the category sShNis(SmS) has guaranteed it con- tains both SmS and S . That is, every representable presheaf is a Nisnevich sheaf, and so by Remark 2.1.23 we have for each X ∈ SmS the associated representable sheaf, a motivic space. Similarly, sShNis(SmS) contains every K ∈ S , in terms of the constant sheaf taking the value K. That is, the simplicial sheaf sending X ↦K for all X ∈ SmS . The category SpcS is (co)complete, and of course has a simplicial structure. Now that we have a new model category of interest, its helpful to know something about the (co)fibrant objects. Proposition 2.2.19. A presheaf F ∈ sShNis(SmS) is fibrant (also called Nisnevich-fibrant) if and 55 only if for every elementary distinguished square U ×X V V U X p i the natural map F(X) → F(V ) ×F(U×XV ) F(U) is a weak equivalence of simplicial sets and F(∅) is a final object. Proof. This is equivalent to saying that the diagram F(X) F(V ) F(U) F(U ×X V ) F(p) F(i) is homotopy cartesian. A definition can be found in [GJ99]. This is also commented on in [AE16] where they refer to multiple other sources for a proof. This is actually a less general version of a result prove in [Bla01, Lemma 4.1] which re- quires the use of cd-structures and proves the result for any site. We present the characterization here: Lemma 2.2.20. [Bla01] A simplicial presheaf X ∈ sShNis(SmS) is fibrant with respect to the local projective model structure if it takes values in Kan complexes and X takes distinguished squares to homotopy cartesian squares. Definition 2.2.21. Presheaves that satisfy this condition are said to satisfy the Brown-Gersten property. There are a lot of results relating to this condition, and we cannot detail all the theory. Definition 2.2.22. The category of pointed motivic spaces, SpcS,∗, is obtained from the above 56 discussion but instead using pointed simplicial presheaves, i.e. presheaves taking values in pointed simplicial sets S∗. The category of pointed motivic spaces is also symmetric monoidal with the construction of the smash product, which we will construct. Remark 2.2.23. We have a pair of adjoint functors between SpcS and SpcS,∗, where ‘going to the right’ provides a disjoint basepoint, and the other functor forgets the basepoint. Definition 2.2.24. We define the wedge product (which is really the coproduct in SpcS,∗) of two pointed spaces (X,x) ∨ (Y, y) to be the pushout of (X,x) ∗ (Y, y) . In terms of pointed simplicial presheaves, this sends a space to the wedge product in pointed simplicial sets of that space. We can also define the smash product (X,x) ∧ (Y, y) = (X,x) × (Y, y)/(X,x) ∨ (Y, y) So now we have a left proper combinatorial simplicial model category structure on SpcS , but it does not have the A1−local properties we want it to have. Most importantly, A1 won’t play the role of the unit interval yet, as A1×SX →X is not guaranteed to be a weak equivalence. This suggests that we need to take another left Bousfield localization. Before proceeding, it would be useful to review Definition 1.3.37. We want to define our A1−local spaces, and then the A1−homotopy category, otherwise known as our unstable motivic category. Definition 2.2.25. Let I be the class of maps in LNis sPsh(SmS) of the form A1 ×S X →X as X ranges over the objects of SmS . Using the fact that SmS is essentially small, pick a subset J ⊂ I where we only range over a representative from each class of isomorphic objects X . The left Bousfield localization with respect to the set J , denoted LA1LNis sPsh(SmS) gives us the A1−local model structure. The homotopy category Ho(LA1LNis sPsh(SmS)) is the A1−homotopy 57 category of S. Notation. Recall that we denote QX,RY as the cofibrant replacement of X and the fibrant re- placement of Y , respectively. Definition 2.2.26. An object X ∈ LA1 LNis sPsh(SmS) is said to be A1−local if it is locally (projective) fibrant and, for any U ∈ SmS we have Map(U × Y,Y ) Map(U,Y )≃loc a local weak equivalence. We say that a map f ∶ X → Y in LA1 LNis sPsh(SmS) is an A1−local weak equivalence if for all A1-local Z, the map Map(QY,Z) Map(U,Z)Qf∗ ≃ is a local weak equivalence. Notation. We also denote SpcA 1 S for LA1LNis sPsh(SmS). Theorem 2.2.27. The category SpcA 1 S is a left proper combinatorial simplicial model category. The weak equivalences of this category are the A1−local weak equivalences, and fibrations are local projective fibrations. Proof. This is immediate from Theorem 1.3.39 and Definition 1.3.38. Notation. For X,Y ∈ sPsh(SmS), the notation [X,Y ]A1 is often used to denote the set of A1- homotopy classes of maps, i.e. maps in Ho(LA1 LNis sPsh(SmS)). Remark 2.2.28. We have a convenient way of characterizing the A1−local objects. Of course, for 58 X ∈ sPsh(SmS) to be A1−local it should satisfy the conditions of being fibrant in sPsh(SmS), SpcS , and SpcA 1 S . We require 1. X(U) is a Kan complex for all U , 2. takes distinguished squares to homotopy cartesian squares, or alternatively satisfies Nis- nevich hyperdescent, 3. X(U)→X(U ×S U) is a local weak equivalence Remark 2.2.29. We now have that A1 is, indeed, contractible in our homotopy category, since X × A1 → X is an A1−weak equivalence. This also gives that An is contractible for all n ≥ 1, since we can just take it as the (fiber) product of contractible spaces. Notation. We often denote H(S) ∶= Ho(LA1 LNis sPsh(SmS)) for the A1homotopy category. Now that we have our A1-homotopy category defined, we should comment on what an A1−homotopy is. Definition 2.2.30. As in classical (unstable) homotopy theory, the motivic spheres allow us to define the bigraded abelian motivic homotopy groups for X ∈ H(S) to be πs,t(X) ∶= [Ss,t,X]H(S). We can do one better than abelian groups, however, with the following construction. Definition 2.2.31. For X ∈ H(S) and U ∈ SmS we can define the (bigraded) motivic homo- topy sheaf of abelian groups πs,t(X) to be the sheafification (in the Nisnevich topology) of the presheaf U ↦ [Ss,t ∧U+,X]H(S), 59 where U+ is ‘given a disjoint basepoint.’ We then recover the unstable homotopy groups as global sections. Remark 2.2.32. It is not uncommon to see the notation [X,Y ]A1 used to signify that we are considering maps up to A1−local homotopy rather than [X,Y ]H(S). More common, however, is suppressing any notation denoting where the equivalence class of maps is taken, as it is usually clear from context. We should comment on the notion of naive, or elementary A1-homotopy. Definition 2.2.33. For f, g ∶ X → Y in SpcS . A naive A1−homotopy from f to g is a map H ∶X ×A1 → Y where we have X × 0 X ×A1 Y X × 1 f H g Remark 2.2.34. Of course, any two maps which are naively A1−homotopic will induce the same morphism in H(S). However, there are far more classes of maps in H(S) than those that arise from a Naive A1−homotopy. This concept is included for the sole purpose of ensuring the reader does not make the misconception that naive A1−homotopies are the correct way of thinking about H(S) 2.3 Stable Motivic Homotopy We wish to construct a stable motivic homotopy category. Before we do so, we need to comment on the sphere objects in motivic homotopy. One of the interesting (and unique) parts of motivic homotopy theory is that we get two spheres, which will end up resulting in a 60 bigraded theory. We make these notions precise over the coming section. The original reference is [Voe98] Definition 2.3.1. We let Gm ∶= A1 ∖ {0} pointed at 1 ∈ Gm. This is called the Tate circle, and it is one of our two motivic circles. The (pre)sheaf represented by the simplicial sphere S1, i.e. the (pre)sheaf represented by ∆1/∂∆1, is called the simplicial circle. Of course, our category has all simplicial n−spheres representing Sn ∶=∆n/∂∆n. With the smash product we remarked in the last section, the natural thing to ask is: what happens when we smash these two motivic circles? The answer to that question is as fol- lows Proposition 2.3.2. P1 is A1-homotopy equivalent to S1 ∧Gm. Proof. P1 is the pushout of A1 Gm A1 . But, as A1 is contractible, we have the homo- topy pushout diagram Gm ∗ ∗ P1 where the homotopy colimit is the suspension S1 ∧Gm. This identifies P1 ≃ S1 ∧Gm. Notation. With a view towards our (bigraded) spectra we will often denote the simplicial sphere as S1 s and the Tate circle as S1 t . We can then simplify notation and list our spheres with a bigrad- ing. That is, Sp,q = (S1 s ∧ S1 s ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ S1 s) ´¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¸¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¶ p−q times ∧ (S1 t ∧ S1 t ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ S1 t ) ´¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¸¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¹¶ q times More compactly, Sp,q = (S1 s)∧p−q ∧ (Gm)∧q. This means that P1 ≃ S2,1 in H(S). 61 We will now give the construction of [DLØ+07], which avoids some of the difficulties asso- ciated to the more popular construction of the stable homotopy category. This uses (s, t)−bispectra, where we are essentially inverting both Ss and St consecutively. We will comment, after showing the alternative construction (P1−spectra), on their equivalence. Definition 2.3.3. An s−spectrum E is a sequence of pointed spaces En ∈ SpcS,∗ with structure maps S1 s ∧En → En+1 A map of s−spectra f ∶ E → F is defined degreewise, fn ∶ En → Fn so that we have a commuta- tive diagram En Fn En+1 Fn+1 fn σn σn fn+1 Definition 2.3.4. The above construction defines the category of s−spectra, denoted Sps(S). Definition 2.3.5. We have an s−suspension spectrum associated to a pointed space X ∈ SpcS,∗, denoted Σ∞s X , defined by (Σ∞s X)n = (S1 s)∧n ∧X , and structure maps identity. This assignment is functorial. We want a proper simplicial stable model category structure on Sps(S). Although, up until this point we have avoided giving a definition for a stable model category, so we should do so here. Definition 2.3.6. Taking the smash product S1 s ∧X is functorial; that is, we have a functor Σs ∶ SpcS,∗ → SpcS,∗ which sends X to S1 s ∧X . This functor is left adjoint to the loop functor, where ΩsX = homSpcS,∗(S1 s ,X) Definition 2.3.7. We say that a model category C is stable if the suspension functor Σs ∶ 62 Ho(C)→ Ho(C) is an equivalence of categories. Alternatively, we can say that the adjunction Σs ∶ Ho(SpcS,∗) Ho(SpcS,∗) ∶ Ωs≅ ≅ form an inverse equivalence between the homotopy categories. Definition 2.3.8. For E ∈ Sps(S), we define the nth sheaf of abelian stable homotopy groups to be the sheaf associated to the presheaf of abelian groups πn(E) ∶= colimm>n πm+n(Em) Remark 2.3.9. This is really the colimit colimm ( . . . π∗+m(E∗) π∗+m+1(ΣE ∗ ) π∗+m+1(E∗+1) . . . Σs σ∗ ) Definition 2.3.10. We say that a morphism of s−spectra f ∶ E → F is an s-stable weak equiva- lence if the induced map f∗ ∶ πn(E)→ πn(F ) is an isomorphism for all n. A morphism of s−spectra is called a stable cofibration if the morphism f0 ∶ E0 → F0 and En+1∐S1∧En S1 ∧ Fn → Fn+1 for n > 0 are both cofibrations. With our notion of weak equivalences and cofibrations, we now wish to define a (proper) simplicial model category structure on Sps(S). Proposition 2.3.11. [Mor03] The category Sps(S) together with s-stable weak equivalences and stable cofibrations (and fibrations defined to have the right lifting property with respect to acyclic cofibrations) forms a proper combinatorial simplicial model category structure. We call this the 63 s-stable model structure. Proof. This can be found in any of [Mor03],[DLØ+07], [MV99] Remark 2.3.12. There is an associated stable homotopy category, denoted SHs, which is ob- tained by taking the left Bousfield localization (with respect to s-stable weak equivalences). We can comment on suspension-loop space adjunction on the stable category Remark 2.3.13. We have the induced adjunction SHs Sps(S) Σ∞ Ω∞ Where the infinite loop space is defined Ω∞(E) ∶= colimn≥0 hom∗(Sn,En) where the notation denotes pointed morphisms. Recall briefly from Definition 2.3.6 we have an adjunction between the suspension and loop space functors on SpcS,∗. This can be extended to an actual adjunction on spectra; our structure maps σn having adjoints ωn giving ωn ∶ En → ΩEn+1. Definition 2.3.14. We say that an S1-spectrum E is an Ω−spectrum if the adjoint ωn ∶ En → ΩEn+1 is a (stable) weak equivalence. We don’t have any of the A1−local properties we would like for our stable category though – mainly, we need A1 to be contractible. Seeing this, we take the only natural next step: localizing in the exact same way as we did with the unstable category. Definition 2.3.15. We say that an s-spectrum E is A1−local if for all U ∈ SmS and n ∈ Z the projection U ×A1 → U defines a bijection HomSHs(Σ∞s U,Σn sF )→ HomSHs(Σ∞s (U ×A1),Σn sF ) 64 A map of s-spectra f ∶ E → F is an A1−local stable weak equivalence if it satisfies the expected condition of Definition 1.3.37. That is, if for any A1−local s-spectrum H , there is a canonical bijection HomSHs(F,H)→ HomSHs(E,H) Proposition 2.3.16. There is a model structure, called the s-stable A1−local model structure on Sps(S) which is obtained by applying Definition 1.3.38, the left Bousfield localization on A1−local weak equivalences to the model structure of Proposition 2.3.11. We denote the category with this model structure as SpA1 s (S), if needed. Proof. This is entirely analogous to our construction of SpcA 1 S . Definition 2.3.17. We have a stable homotopy category associated to our A1-local model struc- ture, which we will simply call the motivic s-stable homotopy category SHA1 s (S). Just inverting with respect to S1,0 isn’t good enough though - we want to invert with respect to Gm as well. This requires us to use the theory of bispectra. Definition 2.3.18. We denote τ ∶ S1 s ∧ S1 t → S1 t ∧ S1 s the isomorphism given by the fact that the smash product is symmetric monoidal on SpcS,∗. Definition 2.3.19. An (s,t)-bispectrum E is a sequence of pointed spaces Ep,q ∈ SpcS,∗ with structure maps σs ∶ S1 s ∧Ep,q → Ep+1,q, σt ∶ S1 t ∧Ep,q → Ep,q+1 65 which are compatible in the sense of the following commutative diagram S1 s ∧ S1 t ∧Ep,q S1 t ∧ S1 s ∧Ep,q S1 s ∧Ep,q+1 Ep+1,q+1 S1 t ∧Ep+1,q id∧σt τ∧id id∧σs σs σt A morphism of bispectra f ∶ E → F is defined level-wise fp,q ∶ Ep,q → Fp,q which commute with structure maps in the obvious way. Bispectra of motivic spaces form a category which we will denote Sps,t(S). Definition 2.3.20. We have a suspension functor Σp,q ∶ Sps,t(S) → Sps,t(S) which acts on E level-wise, sending Er,s to Sp,q ∧ Er,s. It acts on morphisms in the obvious way, i.e. taking the smash with identity. Definition 2.3.21. There is a functor Σ∞s,t ∶ SpcS → Sps,t(S) for which Σ∞Xp,q = (S1 s)∧p ∧ (S1 t )∧q ∧X with structure maps being the identities. We have the expected right adjoint Ω∞s,t The goal with (s, t)−bispectra is to localize at both spheres (using our above construction of s−spectra), so we need a bigraded notion of homotopy sheaves. Definition 2.3.22. For E ∈ Sps,t(S), U ∈ SpcS , and (p, q) ∈ Z2 we define the bigraded stable homotopy sheaves πp,q to be the sheaf associated to the presheaf U ↦ colimmHom SHA1 s (S) (Sp−q s ∧ Sq+m t ∧Σ∞s U, Em) These are sheaves of abelian groups (the category SpA1 s (S) is additive, so the Hom-set has the structure of an abelian group). We assume that q+m ≥ 0. A note on the choice of indices follows below. 66 Remark 2.3.23. As in [DLØ+07], we note that the above definition makes sense when p < q as there is an equivalence of categories SHA1 s (S) SHA1 s (S) S1 s∧− . We also note that, while at first glance the smash Sp−q s ∧ Sq+m t may seem rather unnatural, in our bigraded convention this is just Sp+m,q+m. So, we have emulating our normal definition for stable homotopy. We will again point out that having stable homotopy sheaves is a powerful tool here, and the extra coherence data gives more insight than just stable homotopy groups. We have the obvious notion of a stable weak equivalence. Definition 2.3.24. We say that a map f ∶ E → F in Sps,t(S) is a stable weak equivalence if the induced map f∗ ∶ πp,q(E)→ πp,q(F ) is an isomorphism of sheaves. We say that a morphism f is a stable cofibration if fp,q ∶ Ep,q → Fp,q is a cofibration in the sense of SpcA 1 S,∗, i.e. component-wise. Proposition 2.3.25. The category Sps,t(S) endowed with: 1. weak equivalences the (A1-local) stable weak equivalences, 2. cofibrations the stable cofibrations, 3. fibrations those maps with the right lifting property with respect to the acyclic cofibrations forms a proper stable simplicial model category. Proof. This is [DLØ+07, Remark III.2.11] – but proving this requires no new techniques. It is the same as arguments from before. We are now ready to define our (first version of) the motivic stable homotopy category. Definition 2.3.26. The motivic stable homotopy category SH(S) is the homotopy category of Sps,t(S) with the above stable A1−model structure, SH(S) ∶= Sps,t(S)[sWE−1A1] 67 Remark 2.3.27. The above construction is really just two successive localizations. We could easily write SH(S) = SHA1 s (S)[(Gm)−1], or Sps,t(S)[(S1 s)−1][G−1m ]. The point we are trying to make here is that we can really think of our construction on Sps,t(S) as looking at Gm−spectra of S1 s−spectra. This category is actually symmetric monoidal, but to prove so requires a lot of work – according to Voevodsky, it “takes Adams thirty pages to verify that nothing goes wrong and it is terrible.” [Voe98, p. 594]. Jardine was able to use his theory of symmetric spectra to show that there is a symmetric monoidal structure on SH (really, on symmetric spectra, to which he provides an equivalence) in his work [Jar00]. Proposition 2.3.28 ([Voe98, Theorem 5.6], [Jar00, Theorem 4.31]). SH(S) is a symmetric monoidal category under the smash product of spectra ∧. Proof. Explicitly, [Voe98, Theorem 5.6]. However, there is no explicit proof given; consult [Jar00] for a better reference. [Jar00, Theorem 4.40] gives the required equivalence, and [Jar00, Theorem 4.31] provides the actual construction of the symmetric monoidal stable homotopy cat- egory. 2.4 Another Construction: P1−Spectra Definition 2.4.1. Taking the smash product P1∧X for any space X will be called P1-suspension, often denoted ΣP1X . Definition 2.4.2. A P1−spectrum, also known as a motivic spectrum is a sequence of pointed motivic spaces (E0,E1, . . . ) with structure maps σn ∶ P1 ∧En → En+1 (σn ∶ ΣP1En → En+1). The data here consists of the spaces and the structure maps, so the notation (En, σn) is perhaps better. 68 A map of spectra f ∶ E → F is defined levelwise, i.e. it is a sequence of maps fn ∶ En → Fn which are compatible with the structure maps; that is, we have a commutative diagram P1 ∧En En+1 P1 ∧ F n F n+1 σE n id∧fn fn+1 σF n Of course, P1 is pointed at∞. We can use the more compact notation of (P1,∞) Having defined objects and morphisms, we are forced to make the following definition: Definition 2.4.3. We denote SpP1(S) for the category of P1−spectra, also called the category of motivic spectra. Example 2.4.4. The most basic example of a P1 spectrum is the suspension spectrum Σ∞P1(X ) for any X ∈ SpcS,∗. This is better than just an example, though: Definition 2.4.5. Σ∞P1 ∶ SpcA 1 S,∗ → SpP1(S) defines a functor We now want to endow P1-spectra with a proper simplicial model category structure in order to form the stable homotopy category of motivic spaces. In his original work [Voe98], Vo- evodsky gives a detour on (s, t)-bispectra , which eventually culminates in the definition of the motivic stable homotopy category. There is another way of constructing the stable motivic homo- topy category due to Jardine’s theory of motivic symmetric spectra, presented in [Jar00]. We can now define the stable motivic homotopy sheaves. This is analogous to the construc- tion in the case of (s, t)−bispectra. Definition 2.4.6 ([Mor03]). Let E an object in SpP1(S), U ∈ SmS , and (n,m) ∈ Z2. We define the motivic stable homotopy sheaf, denoted πst s,t(E) to be the (Nisnevich) sheafification of the 69 presheaf defined by U ↦ colimrHomH(S)(Ss+r s ∧ (U+) ∧ (P1)r−t,Er) Definition 2.4.7. The motivic stable homotopy groups are defined to be the global sections of the motivic stable homotopy sheaves, and give abelian groups. For X ∈ SpP1(S) and U ∈ SmS we have, πs,t(X)(U) ∶= colimrHomH(S)●(Ss+t s ∧ (X+) ∧ (P1)r−t,Er) Definition 2.4.8 ([Mor03]). A morphism f ∶ E → F in SpP1(S) is called an A1−stable weak equivalence if for any X ∈ SmS and any (n,m) ∈ Z2 the homomorphism f∗∶πn,m(E)→ πn,m(F ) is an isomorphism Definition 2.4.9. In the construction of [Jar00], a map f ∶ E → F in SpP1(S) is a 1. level weak equivalence if fn ∶ En → Fn is a weak equivalence in SpcS for all n ≥ 0, 2. level fibration if fn ∶ En → Fn is a cofibration in SpcS for all n ≥ 0, 3. cofibration if it has the left lifting property with respect to acyclic levelwise fibrations. The model structure on SpP1(S) is then defined by level weak equivalences, level fibrations, and cofibrations. Theorem 2.4.10 ([Jar00]). The category SpP1(S) endowed with level weak equivalences, level fibrations, and cofibrations as in Definition 2.4.9 gives a proper simplicial model category. Proof. This is [Jar00, Lemma 2.1]. 70 Definition 2.4.11. A map of P1 spectra f ∶ E → F is said to be a motivic stable weak equiva- lence if the induced map f∗ ∶ πst s,t(E)→ πst s,t(F ) is an isomorphism of sheaves. Proposition 2.4.12. The category SpP1(S) together with 1. Weak equivalences the motivic stable weak equivalences 2. Cofibrations the levelwise cofibrations of Definition 2.4.9 forms a proper simplicial model category. Proof. This is [Jar00, Theorem 9.2]. Definition 2.4.13. We define the stable motivic homotopy category SH(S) to be the localiza- tion of SpP1(S) with respect to the model structure of Proposition 2.4.12 SH(S) ∶= SpP1(S)[(P1 ∧ −)−1] This is often treated as “the” motivic stable homotopy category; we will sometimes use the nota- tion SHP1(S) if we need to compare to the construction of the previous section. Proposition 2.4.14. There is an adjunction SHA1 s (S) SHP1(S) ω∞ σ∞ 71 which gives an equivalence of stable homotopy categories, SHA1 s (S)[G−1m ] SH(S)≃ Proof. This is a simple observation by construction of the two categories and the stated adjunc- tion. This can be found, for example, in [ABH23]. Remark 2.4.15. With the above proposition we have shown that the two constructions give us an equivalent motivic stable homotopy category. It is standard to work with the P1−construction. Remark 2.4.16. In the interest of simplifying notation and presentation, it is often written that H(S)[[P1]−1] = SH(S). By this we of course mean passing to P1−spectra, and then formally inverting suspension. We get the standard adjunction H(S) SH(S). Σ∞ P1